|
Реферат: A role of the Environmental Ethics in the modern society
Реферат: A role of the Environmental Ethics in the modern society
Executed by: student TBA-40 group Radchenko
Nataliya
Faculty: direction and television
KYIV-2000
The inspiration for environmental ethics was the first Earth Day in
1970 when environmentalists started urging philosophers who were involved with
environmental groups to do something about environmental ethics. An
intellectual climate had developed in the last few years of the 1960s in large
part because of the publication of two papers in Science: Lynn White`s “The
Historical Roots of our Ecological Crisis” (March 1967) and Garett Hardin`s
"The Tragedy of the Commons" (December 1968). Most influential with
regard to this kind of thinking, however, was an essay in Aldo Leopold`s A Sand
County Almanac, "The Land Ethic," in which Leopold explicitly claimed
that the roots of the ecological crisis were philosophical. Although originally
published in 1949, Sand County Almanac became widely available in 1970 in a
special Sierra Club/Ballantine edition, which included essays from a second
book, Round River.
Most academic activity in the 1970s was spent debating the Lynn
White thesis and the tragedy of the commons. These debates were primarily
historical, theological, and religious, not philosophical. Throughout most of
the decade philosophers sat on the sidelines trying to determine what a field
called environmental ethics might look like. The first philosophical conference
was organized by William Blackstone at the University of Georgia in 1972. The
proceedings were published as Philosophy and Environmental Crisis in 1974,
which included Pete Gunter`s first paper on the Big Thicket. In 1972 a book
called “Is It Too Late?” A Theology of Ecology, written by John B. Cobb, was
published. It was the first single-authored book written by a philosopher, even
though the primary focus of the book was theological and religious. In 1973 an
Australian philosopher, Richard Routley (now Sylvan), presented a paper at the
15th World Congress of Philosophy "Is There a Need for a New, an
Environmental, Ethic?" A year later John Passmore, another Australian,
wrote Man’s Responsibility for Nature, in which, reacting to Routley, he argued
that there was no need for an environmental ethic at all. Most debates among
philosophers until the mid-1980s was focused on refuting Passmore. In 1975
environmental ethics came to the attention of mainstream philosophy with the
publication of Holmes Rolston, III`s paper, "Is There an Ecological
Ethic?" in Ethics.
Arne Naess, a Norwegian philosopher and the founding editor of the
journal Inquiry authored and published a paper in Inquiry “The Shallow and the
Deep, Long-range Ecology Movement” in 1973, which was the beginning of the deep
ecology movement. Important writers in this movement include George Sessions,
Bill DeVall, Warwick Fox, and, in some respects, Max Oelschlaeger.
Throughout the 1970s Inquiry was the primary philosophy journal that
dealt with environmental ethics. Environmental ethics was, for the most part,
considered a curiosity and mainstream philosophy journals rarely published more
than one article per year, if that. Opportunities for publishing dramatically
improved in 1979 when Eugene C. Hargrove founded the journal Environmental
Ethics. The name of the journal became the name of the field.
The first five years of the journal was spent mostly arguing about
rights for nature and the relationship of environmental ethics and animal
rights/animal liberation. Rights lost and animal welfare ethics was determined
to be a separate field. Animal rights has since developed as a separate field
with a separate journal, first, Ethics and Animals, which was later superseded
by Between the Species.
Cobb published another book in the early 1980s, The Liberation of
Life with co-author Charles Birch. This book took a process philosophy approach
in accordance with the philosophy of organism of Alfred North Whitehead. Robin
Attfield, a philosopher in Wales, wrote a book called The Ethics of
Environmental Concern. It was the first full-length response to Passmore. An
anthology of papers, Ethics and the Environment, was edited by Donald Scherer
and Tom Attig.
There was a turning point about 1988 when many single-authored books
began to come available: Paul Taylor`s Respect for Nature; Holmes Rolston`s
Environmental Ethics; Mark Sagoff`s The Economy of the Earth; and Eugene C.
Hargrove`s Foundations of Environmental Ethics. J. Baird Callicott created a
collection of his papers, In Defence of the Land Ethic. Bryan Norton wrote Why
Preserve Natural Diversity? followed more recently by Toward Unity among
Environmentalists. A large number of books have been written by Kristin
Shrader-Frechette on economics and policy.
In the 1980s a second movement, ecofeminism, developed. Karen Warren
is the key philosopher, although the ecofeminism movement involves many
thinkers from other fields. It was then followed by a third, social ecology,
based on the views of Murray Bookchin. An important link between academics and
radical environmentalists was established with the creation of the Canadian
deep ecology journal, The Trumpeter. In 1989, Earth Ethics Quarterly was begun
as a more popular environmental publication. Originally intended primarily as a
reprint publication, now as a publication of the Centre for Respect for Life
and Environment, it is focused more on international sustainable development.
The 1990s began with the establishment of the International Society
for Environmental Ethics, which was founded largely through the efforts of
Laura Westra and Holmes Rolston, III. It now has members throughout the world.
In 1992, a second refereed philosophy journal, dedicated to environmental
ethics, Environmental Values published its first issue in England.
On the theoretical level, Taylor and Rolston, despite many
disagreements, can be regarded as objective nonanthropocentric intrinsic value
theorists. Callicott, who follows Aldo Leopold closely, is a subjective
nonanthropocentric intrinsic value theorist. Hargrove is considered a weak
anthropocentric intrinsic value theorist. Sagoff is very close to this position
although he doesn’t talk about intrinsic value much and takes a Kantian rather
than an Aristotlian approach. At the far end is Bryan Norton who thought up
weak anthropocentrism but wants to replace intrinsic value with a pragmatic
conception of value.
A brief history of environmental consciousness in the western world
places our views in perspective and provides a context for understanding the
maze of related and unrelated thoughts, philosophies, and practices that we
call "environmentalism." Understanding where the questions being
asked and analyzed are coming from is essential in environmental analysis: the
kinds of questions asked by an environmental group and their interpretation of
the results can be vastly different from, for example, a utility, logging
company or special interest (ranchers grazing public lands, and so forth).
The term "environmental ethics," in fact the whole field,
is a very recent phenomenum, actually only several decades old, although many
particular concerns or philosophical threads have been developing for several
centuries. A Professor named Eugene Hargroves began a journal he named Environmental
Ethics in the late 1970s in which controversies regarding environmental
behaviour and visions could be discussed. This name became an umbrella for a
group of strange bedfellows. A controversy had begun in 1974 when an Australian
named John Passmore published a book called "Man`s responsibility for
nature: ecological problems and western traditions" in which he argued
that environmental preservation and concern was inconsistent with western
tradition. Robin Attfield replied 1983 in a book entitled "The ethics of
environmental concern" by holding that the stewardship tradition was more
important than dominion in western thought, and that this is what forms the
foundation for environmental ethics. Environmental ethics is a collection of
independent ethical generalizations, not a tight, rationally ordered set of
rules. Environmental ethics will be a compilation of interrelated independent
guidelines - a process field that will be coming together for a long time.
Ethics really flow from peoples perceptions, attitudes and behaviour
- as in the case of environmental ethics and animal liberation. Like chess,
decision making in life is very perceptual or intuitive - by analogy, there are
l) favourite formations (of players or arguments); 2) empirical investigation
of these (with maximum and minimum expectations); which leads to a progressive
deepening of perspective.
The problem is only dimly perceived in the beginning, but becomes
clearer with thought and re-examination. What holds a chess game together is
not the rules but the experience the individual player. A grand master at chess
sees more on a chessboard in a few seconds than an average player sees in
thirty minutes.
Environmental ethics today encompasses a diverse, not necessarily
related, anthology including:
1. Animal rights.
2. The Land Ethic.
3. Ecofeminism.
4. Deep Ecology.
5. Shallow Ecology.
6. The rights of rocks, and so forth.
8. Bioethics.
Bioethics could be defined as the study of ethical issues and
decision-making associated with the use of living organisms and medicine. It
includes both medical ethics and environmental ethics. Rather than defining a
correct decision it is about the process of decision-making balancing different
benefits, risks and duties. The word "bioethics" was first used in
1970, however, the concept of bioethics is much older, as we can see in the
ethics formulated and debated in literature, art, music and the general
cultural and religious traditions of our ancestors.
Society is facing many important decisions about the use of science
and technology. These decisions affect the environment, human health, society
and international policy. To resolve these issues, and develop principles to
help us make decisions we need to involve anthropology, sociology, biology,
medicine, religion, psychology, philosophy, and economics; we must combine the
scientific rigour of biological data, with the values of religion and
philosophy to develop a world-view. Bioethics is therefore challenged to be a
multi-sided and thoughtful approach to decision-making so that it may be
relevant to all aspects of human life.
The term bioethics reminds us of the combination of biology and
ethics, topics that are intertwined. New technology can be a catalyst for our
thinking about issues of life, and we can think of the examples like assisted
reproductive technologies, life sustaining technology, organ transplantation,
and genetics, which have been stimuli for research into bioethics in the last
few decades. Another stimulus has been the environmental problems.
There are large and small problems in ethics. We can think of
problems that involve the whole world, and problems which involve a single
person. We can think of global problems, such as the depletion of the ozone
layer which is increasing UV radiation affecting all living organisms. This
problem could be solved by individual action to stop using ozone-depleting
chemicals, if alternatives are available to consumers. However, global action
was taken to control the problem. The international convention to stop the
production of many ozone-depleting chemicals is one of the best examples yet of
applying universal environmental ethics.
Another problem is greenhouse warming, which results mainly from
energy use. This problem however can only be solved by individual action to
reduce energy use, because we cannot easily ban the use of energy. We could do
this by turning off lights, turning down heaters and air conditioners, building
more energy efficient buildings, shutting doors, and driving with a light foot.
These are all simple actions which everyone must do if we are concerned about
our planet, yet not many do so. Energy consumption could be reduced 50-80% by
lifestyle change with current technology if people wanted to. New technology
may help, but lifestyle change can have much more immediate affect.
Environmental ethics is a relatively new field - and the name
"environmental ethics" derives from Eugene Hargrove`s journal, which
was begun in late 1970s.
This field - environmental ethics, - will be subsumed as other areas
of applied ethics develop more fully. The early pieces or threads of
environmental ethics were disconnected...one needs a quick review to fully
comprehend today`s "whole" - and know the directions in which the
threads lead.
Environmental ethicists as well as policy-makers, activists etc.
frequently speak about the need for preservation of various parts of nature.
Two main grounds are repeatedly presented for this need:
1. Our moral responsibilities to future human beings (sometimes
called sustainable development) require that we stop using technology and
science for short-term gains at the expense of long-term risks of very negative
ecological effects for future people. In several official declarations and
policy-documents this idea has been expressed as "the precautionary
principle", roughly the idea that we should not use particular means of
production, distribution etc. unless they have been shown not to effect too
serious risks. However, it is far from clear what is meant by this. What
determines whether or not the effecting of a certain risk (in order to secure
some short-term gain) is too serious or not? - and what determines whether or
not this has been "shown"? Some traditional decision-theorists would
say that it is a question of traditional instrumental efficiency (i.e.
rationality) in relation to morally respectable aims. Some ethicists would
instead claim that it is a question of whether or not the severity of the
scenario illustrating an actualization of the risk in question makes the taking
of this risk morally wrong in itself. Others, yet, hint that they want to take
a stand in between these two extremes, however, without specifying what this
could mean. There is also a rather grim debate regarding whether or not it can
ever be shown that a certain action does not effect too serious risks, and this
of course depends on what requirements should be laid on someone who purports
to show such a thing. In both cases, the questions seem to boil down to basic
issues regarding what is required of risky decisions in order to make them
morally justified. But, obviously, it must be a kind of moral justification
different from the one dealt with by traditional ethical theories of the rights
and wrongs of actions, since these only deal with justification in terms of
actual outcomes, not in terms of risks for such outcomes.
2. Natural systems possess a value in themselves which makes them
worth preserving also at the expense of human well-being and man-made
constructs. This idea is less common in official documents than the former
(although it is explicitely set out as a part of the basis of the Swedish
Environmental Policy Act) than it is among environmental philosophers and
ethicists. However, also this idea is far from clear, since it is not clear
neither how a natural system is to be distinguished from a non-natural one and
why this difference is to be taken as morally relevant, nor why preservation is
the only recommendation which follows from the placing of an intrinsic value in
nature. Although there are several suggestion on what it is that makes certain
systems intrinsically valuable, it is has not been sufficiently explained,
first, why these characteristics (typically complexity, self-preservation/replication,
beauty etc.) do not justify preservation also of systems normally not taken to
be natural (such as metropolitan areas, hamburger restaurants or nuclear
power-plants), secondly, why this value does not imply a recommendation to reshape
rather than preserve natural systems, in order to increase the presence and
magnitude of the value-making characteristics. In particular, it seems to be a
challenge for a preservationist to argue in favour of restoration of certain
biotic variants, without leaving the door open also for reshaping, for example
by the use of modern biotechnology.
The aim of this research-project is to attack these two families of
issues, both connected to the justification of common ideas regarding the
importance of preserving various parts of nature. In one part (carried out by
christian menthe), the project will be aimed at mapping out moral intuitions
regarding the moral responsibility of the taking of risks, in order to use
these for developing a normative theory of the morality of risk-taking which
can be used to underpin a more specific version of the precautionary principle.
The other part of the project is instead aimed at systematically reviewing
various proposals (and new home-made to how to distinguish between that (i.e.
nature)) which should typically be preserved according to preservationists and
that which does not need to be so preserved, and to resist the conclusion that
reshaping of nature might be a better idea from the point of view of typically
preservationist values than actual preservation. The focus here will be on
ideas ascribing a value in itself to nature or certain natural systems.
Список литературы
1. Charles Birch and John B. Cobb, Jr., The Liberation of Life: From
the Cell to the Community (Denton, Tex.:
Environmental Ethics Books, 1990), 357 pages.
2. Yrjo Sepanmaa, The Beauty of Environment: A General Model for
Environmental Aesthetics, 2d ed. (Denton, Tex.: Environmental Ethics Books,
1993), 191 pages.
3. John B. Cobb, Jr., Is It Too Late? A Theology of Ecology, rev.
ed. (Denton, Tex.: Environmental Ethics Books, 1995), 112 pages.
4. Eugene C. Hargrove, Foundations of Environmental Ethics (reprint
ed., Denton, Tex.: Environmental Ethics Books, 1996), 229 pages.
5. Robin Attfield, The Ethics of Environmental Concern (Denton,
Tex.: Environmental Ethics Books, 1983), 237 pages.
Для
подготовки данной работы были использованы материалы с сайта http://referatfrom.ru/
|